enow.com Web Search

Search results

  1. Results from the WOW.Com Content Network
  2. Open formula - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Open_formula

    An open formula can be transformed into a closed formula by applying a quantifier for each free variable. This transformation is called capture of the free variables to make them bound variables. For example, when reasoning about natural numbers, the formula "x+2 > y" is open, since it contains the free variables x and y.

  3. Sentence (mathematical logic) - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Sentence_(mathematical_logic)

    A sentence can be viewed as expressing a proposition, something that must be true or false. The restriction of having no free variables is needed to make sure that sentences can have concrete, fixed truth values: as the free variables of a (general) formula can range over several values, the truth value of such a formula may vary.

  4. Quantifier (logic) - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Quantifier_(logic)

    In logic, a quantifier is an operator that specifies how many individuals in the domain of discourse satisfy an open formula. For instance, the universal quantifier ∀ {\displaystyle \forall } in the first order formula ∀ x P ( x ) {\displaystyle \forall xP(x)} expresses that everything in the domain satisfies the property denoted by P ...

  5. Propositional variable - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Propositional_variable

    Example. In a given propositional logic, a formula can be defined as follows: Every propositional variable is a formula. Given a formula X, the negation ¬X is a formula. Given two formulas X and Y, and a binary connective b (such as the logical conjunction ∧), the expression (X b Y) is a formula. (Note the parentheses.)

  6. Propositional calculus - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Propositional_calculus

    Example of a truth table A graphical representation of a partially built propositional tableau Semantic proof systems rely on the concept of semantic consequence, symbolized as φ ⊨ ψ {\displaystyle \varphi \models \psi } , which indicates that if φ {\displaystyle \varphi } is true, then ψ {\displaystyle \psi } must also be true in every ...

  7. First-order logic - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/First-order_logic

    Example requires a quantifier over predicates, which cannot be implemented in single-sorted first-order logic: Zj → ∃X(Xj∧Xp). Quantification over properties Santa Claus has all the attributes of a sadist. Example requires quantifiers over predicates, which cannot be implemented in single-sorted first-order logic: ∀X(∀x(Sx → Xx) → ...

  8. Decidability of first-order theories of the real numbers

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Decidability_of_first...

    It is an open problem whether this theory is decidable, but if Schanuel's conjecture holds then the decidability of this theory would follow. [ 2 ] [ 3 ] In contrast, the extension of the theory of real closed fields with the sine function is undecidable since this allows encoding of the undecidable theory of integers (see Richardson's theorem ).

  9. Logical constant - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Logical_constant

    Two important types of logical constants are logical connectives and quantifiers. The equality predicate (usually written '=') is also treated as a logical constant in many systems of logic . One of the fundamental questions in the philosophy of logic is "What is a logical constant?"; [ 1 ] that is, what special feature of certain constants ...