enow.com Web Search

Search results

  1. Results from the WOW.Com Content Network
  2. Axiom of choice - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Axiom_of_choice

    A uniform space is compact if and only if it is complete and totally bounded. Every Tychonoff space has a Stone–Čech compactification. Mathematical logic. Gödel's completeness theorem for first-order logic: every consistent set of first-order sentences has a completion. That is, every consistent set of first-order sentences can be extended ...

  3. Compactness theorem - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Compactness_theorem

    In mathematical logic, the compactness theorem states that a set of first-order sentences has a model if and only if every finite subset of it has a model. This theorem is an important tool in model theory, as it provides a useful (but generally not effective) method for constructing models of any set of sentences that is finitely consistent.

  4. Probability space - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Probability_space

    In order to provide a model of probability, these elements must satisfy probability axioms. In the example of the throw of a standard die, The sample space is typically the set {,,,,,} where each element in the set is a label which represents the outcome of the die landing on that label.

  5. Logic of graphs - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Logic_of_graphs

    There are several variations in the types of logical operation that can be used in these sentences. The first-order logic of graphs concerns sentences in which the variables and predicates concern individual vertices and edges of a graph, while monadic second-order graph logic allows quantification over sets of vertices or edges.

  6. Sample space - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Sample_space

    A sample space is usually denoted using set notation, and the possible ordered outcomes, or sample points, [5] are listed as elements in the set. It is common to refer to a sample space by the labels S, Ω, or U (for "universal set"). The elements of a sample space may be numbers, words, letters, or symbols.

  7. First-order logic - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/First-order_logic

    In this example, both sentences happen to have the common form () for some individual , in the first sentence the value of the variable x is "Socrates", and in the second sentence it is "Plato". Due to the ability to speak about non-logical individuals along with the original logical connectives, first-order logic includes propositional logic.

  8. Structure (mathematical logic) - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Structure_(mathematical_logic)

    In the case of model theory these axioms have the form of first-order sentences. The formalism of universal algebra is much more restrictive; essentially it only allows first-order sentences that have the form of universally quantified equations between terms, e.g. x y (x + y = y + x). One consequence is that the choice of a signature is more ...

  9. Second-order logic - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Second-order_logic

    As a result, second-order logic has greater expressive power than first-order logic. For example, there is no way in first-order logic to identify the set of all cubes and tetrahedrons. But the existence of this set can be asserted in second-order logic as: ∃P ∀x (Px ↔ (Cube(x) ∨ Tet(x))). We can then assert properties of this set.