enow.com Web Search

Search results

  1. Results from the WOW.Com Content Network
  2. Logical consequence - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Logical_consequence

    Consider the modal account in terms of the argument given as an example above: All frogs are green. Kermit is a frog. Therefore, Kermit is green. The conclusion is a logical consequence of the premises because we can not imagine a possible world where (a) all frogs are green; (b) Kermit is a frog; and (c) Kermit is not green.

  3. Textual entailment - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Textual_entailment

    Textual entailment can be illustrated with examples of three different relations: [5] An example of a positive TE (text entails hypothesis) is: text: If you help the needy, God will reward you. hypothesis: Giving money to a poor man has good consequences. An example of a negative TE (text contradicts hypothesis) is:

  4. Entailment (linguistics) - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Entailment_(linguistics)

    For example, the sentence "The king of France is bald" presupposes that there is a king of France. Unlike an entailment, presuppositions survive when the sentence is negated. The negation test can be used to determine the difference between entailment and presupposition. [ 4 ]

  5. Paradoxes of material implication - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Paradoxes_of_material...

    An argument (consisting of premises and a conclusion) is valid if and only if there is no possible situation in which all the premises are true and the conclusion is false. For example a valid argument might run: If it is raining, water exists (1st premise) It is raining (2nd premise) Water exists (Conclusion)

  6. Propositional calculus - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Propositional_calculus

    Conclusion: It's cloudy. The logical form of this argument is known as modus ponens , [ 39 ] which is a classically valid form. [ 40 ] So, in classical logic, the argument is valid , although it may or may not be sound , depending on the meteorological facts in a given context.

  7. Hypothetical syllogism - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hypothetical_syllogism

    A pure hypothetical syllogism is a syllogism in which both premises and the conclusion are all conditional statements. The antecedent of one premise must match the consequent of the other for the conditional to be valid. Consequently, conditionals contain remained antecedent as antecedent and remained consequent as consequent. If P, then Q.

  8. Non-monotonic logic - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Non-monotonic_logic

    A non-monotonic logic is a formal logic whose entailment relation is not monotonic.In other words, non-monotonic logics are devised to capture and represent defeasible inferences, i.e., a kind of inference in which reasoners draw tentative conclusions, enabling reasoners to retract their conclusion(s) based on further evidence. [1]

  9. Validity (logic) - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Validity_(logic)

    The conclusion is a necessary consequence of its premises. An argument that is not valid is said to be "invalid". An example of a valid (and sound) argument is given by the following well-known syllogism: All men are mortal. (True) Socrates is a man. (True) Therefore, Socrates is mortal. (True)