enow.com Web Search

Search results

  1. Results from the WOW.Com Content Network
  2. Cantor's theorem - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Cantor's_theorem

    Cantor's theorem and its proof are closely related to two paradoxes of set theory. Cantor's paradox is the name given to a contradiction following from Cantor's theorem together with the assumption that there is a set containing all sets, the universal set. In order to distinguish this paradox from the next one discussed below, it is important ...

  3. Cantor's diagonal argument - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Cantor's_diagonal_argument

    An illustration of Cantor's diagonal argument (in base 2) for the existence of uncountable sets. The sequence at the bottom cannot occur anywhere in the enumeration of sequences above. An infinite set may have the same cardinality as a proper subset of itself, as the depicted bijection f(x)=2x from the natural to the even numbers demonstrates ...

  4. Controversy over Cantor's theory - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Controversy_over_Cantor's...

    So Cantor's argument implies that the set of all subsets of N has greater cardinality than N. The set of all subsets of N is denoted by P ( N ), the power set of N . Cantor generalized his argument to an arbitrary set A and the set consisting of all functions from A to {0, 1}. [ 4 ]

  5. Continuum hypothesis - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Continuum_hypothesis

    Cantor gave two proofs that the cardinality of the set of integers is strictly smaller than that of the set of real numbers (see Cantor's first uncountability proof and Cantor's diagonal argument). His proofs, however, give no indication of the extent to which the cardinality of the integers is less than that of the real numbers.

  6. Paradoxes of set theory - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Paradoxes_of_set_theory

    However, Cantor's theorem proves that there are uncountable sets. The root of this seeming paradox is that the countability or noncountability of a set is not always absolute, but can depend on the model in which the cardinality is measured. It is possible for a set to be uncountable in one model of set theory but countable in a larger model ...

  7. Cantor's paradox - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Cantor's_paradox

    This fact is a direct consequence of Cantor's theorem on the cardinality of the power set of a set. Proof: Assume the contrary, and let C be the largest cardinal number. Then (in the von Neumann formulation of cardinality) C is a set and therefore has a power set 2 C which, by Cantor's theorem, has cardinality strictly larger than C .

  8. Set theory - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Set_theory

    This theorem is proved using Cantor's first uncountability proof, which differs from the more familiar proof using his diagonal argument. Cantor introduced fundamental constructions in set theory, such as the power set of a set A, which is the set of all possible subsets of A. He later proved that the size of the power set of A is strictly ...

  9. Cardinal assignment - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Cardinal_assignment

    The oldest definition of the cardinality of a set X (implicit in Cantor and explicit in Frege and Principia Mathematica) is as the set of all sets that are equinumerous with X: this does not work in ZFC or other related systems of axiomatic set theory because this collection is too large to be a set, but it does work in type theory and in New ...