enow.com Web Search

Search results

  1. Results from the WOW.Com Content Network
  2. Resolution (logic) - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Resolution_(logic)

    In first-order logic, resolution condenses the traditional syllogisms of logical inference down to a single rule. To understand how resolution works, consider the following example syllogism of term logic: All Greeks are Europeans. Homer is a Greek. Therefore, Homer is a European. Or, more generally: .

  3. WFF 'N PROOF - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/WFF_'N_PROOF

    All players must be able to recognize a "well-formed formula" (WFF in Łukasiewicz notation), to assemble dice values into valid statements (WFFs) and to apply the rules of logical inference so as to complete a proof. [1] Games are played by two or more people. The first player to roll the cubes sets a WFF as a Goal.

  4. List of rules of inference - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/List_of_rules_of_inference

    Each logic operator can be used in an assertion about variables and operations, showing a basic rule of inference. Examples: The column-14 operator (OR), shows Addition rule: when p=T (the hypothesis selects the first two lines of the table), we see (at column-14) that p∨q=T.

  5. Universal instantiation - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Universal_instantiation

    In predicate logic, universal instantiation [1] [2] [3] (UI; also called universal specification or universal elimination, [citation needed] and sometimes confused with dictum de omni) [citation needed] is a valid rule of inference from a truth about each member of a class of individuals to the truth about a particular individual of that class.

  6. Validity (logic) - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Validity_(logic)

    A statement can be called valid, i.e. logical truth, in some systems of logic like in Modal logic if the statement is true in all interpretations. In Aristotelian logic statements are not valid per se. Validity refers to entire arguments. The same is true in propositional logic (statements can be true or false but not called valid or invalid).

  7. Rule of inference - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Rule_of_inference

    This is the modus ponens rule of propositional logic. Rules of inference are often formulated as schemata employing metavariables. [2] In the rule (schema) above, the metavariables A and B can be instantiated to any element of the universe (or sometimes, by convention, a restricted subset such as propositions) to form an infinite set of ...

  8. Universal generalization - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Universal_generalization

    The full generalization rule allows for hypotheses to the left of the turnstile, but with restrictions. Assume Γ {\displaystyle \Gamma } is a set of formulas, φ {\displaystyle \varphi } a formula, and Γ ⊢ φ ( y ) {\displaystyle \Gamma \vdash \varphi (y)} has been derived.

  9. Obversion - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Obversion

    In traditional logic, obversion is a "type of immediate inference in which from a given proposition another proposition is inferred whose subject is the same as the original subject, whose predicate is the contradictory of the original predicate, and whose quality is affirmative if the original proposition's quality was negative and vice versa". [1]