Search results
Results from the WOW.Com Content Network
The logarithm of an infinite cardinal number κ is defined as the least cardinal number μ such that κ ≤ 2 μ. Logarithms of infinite cardinals are useful in some fields of mathematics, for example in the study of cardinal invariants of topological spaces, though they lack some of the properties that logarithms of positive real numbers possess.
The continuum hypothesis says that =, i.e. is the smallest cardinal number bigger than , i.e. there is no set whose cardinality is strictly between that of the integers and that of the real numbers. The continuum hypothesis is independent of ZFC , a standard axiomatization of set theory; that is, it is impossible to prove the continuum ...
In set theory, a regular cardinal is a cardinal number that is equal to its own cofinality. More explicitly, this means that κ {\displaystyle \kappa } is a regular cardinal if and only if every unbounded subset C ⊆ κ {\displaystyle C\subseteq \kappa } has cardinality κ {\displaystyle \kappa } .
The use of Scott's trick for cardinal numbers shows how the method is typically employed. The initial definition of a cardinal number is an equivalence class of sets, where two sets are equivalent if there is a bijection between them.
The von Neumann cardinal assignment is a cardinal assignment that uses ordinal numbers. For a well-orderable set U , we define its cardinal number to be the smallest ordinal number equinumerous to U , using the von Neumann definition of an ordinal number.
The goal of a cardinal assignment is to assign to every set A a specific, unique set that is only dependent on the cardinality of A. This is in accordance with Cantor 's original vision of cardinals: to take a set and abstract its elements into canonical "units" and collect these units into another set, such that the only thing special about ...
The cardinality of a set X is essentially a measure of the number of elements of the set. [1] Equinumerosity has the characteristic properties of an equivalence relation (reflexivity, symmetry, and transitivity): [1] Reflexivity Given a set A, the identity function on A is a bijection from A to itself, showing that every set A is equinumerous ...
Notably, ℵ ω is the first uncountable cardinal number that can be demonstrated within Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory not to be equal to the cardinality of the set of all real numbers 2 ℵ 0: For any natural number n ≥ 1, we can consistently assume that 2 ℵ 0 = ℵ n, and moreover it is possible to assume that 2 ℵ 0 is as least as large ...