enow.com Web Search

Search results

  1. Results from the WOW.Com Content Network
  2. Aristotle's theory of universals - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Aristotle's_theory_of...

    In Aristotle's view, universals are incorporeal and universal, but only exist only where they are instantiated; they exist only in things. [1] Aristotle said that a universal is identical in each of its instances. All red things are similar in that there is the same universal, redness, in each thing.

  3. Predication (philosophy) - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Predication_(philosophy)

    Aristotle said that predication can be kath hauto when the predicated universal identifies the subject as what it is, marking this type as de re necessary. [ 23 ] [ 24 ] It is distinguished from kata sumbebekos predication, which is concerned with how-predication or when the predicated universal merely modifies or characterizes a subject that ...

  4. Aristotelianism - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Aristotelianism

    Universals without instances are not part of the world. [37] Taking a realist approach to universals also allows an Aristotelian realist philosophy of mathematics, according to which mathematics is a science of properties that are instantiated in the real (including physical) world, such as quantitative and structural properties. [38]

  5. Problem of universals - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Problem_of_universals

    A biologist can study oak trees and learn about oakness and more generally the intelligible order within the sensible world. Accordingly, Aristotle was more confident than Plato about coming to know the sensible world; he was a prototypical empiricist and a founder of induction. Aristotle was a new, moderate sort of realist about universals.

  6. Universal (metaphysics) - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Universal_(metaphysics)

    In metaphysics, a universal is what particular things have in common, namely characteristics or qualities. In other words, universals are repeatable or recurrent entities that can be instantiated or exemplified by many particular things. [1] For example, suppose there are two chairs in a room, each of which is green.

  7. Theory of categories - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Theory_of_categories

    They were held to be just 'subsisting' while such a status was denied to universals. [16] Thus, they accepted Anaxagoras's idea (as did Aristotle) that if an object is hot, it is because some part of a universal heat body had entered the object. But, unlike Aristotle, they extended the idea to cover all chance incidents. Thus, if an object is ...

  8. Categories (Aristotle) - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Categories_(Aristotle)

    The Categories (Greek Κατηγορίαι Katēgoriai; Latin Categoriae or Praedicamenta) is a text from Aristotle's Organon that enumerates all the possible kinds of things that can be the subject or the predicate of a proposition. They are "perhaps the single most heavily discussed of all Aristotelian notions". [1]

  9. Square of opposition - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Square_of_opposition

    The A proposition, the universal affirmative (universalis affirmativa), whose form in Latin is 'omne S est P ', usually translated as 'every S is a P '. The E proposition, the universal negative (universalis negativa), Latin form 'nullum S est P ', usually translated as 'no S are P '.