enow.com Web Search

Search results

  1. Results from the WOW.Com Content Network
  2. Power set - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Power_set

    The power set of the set of natural numbers can be put in a one-to-one correspondence with the set of real numbers (see Cardinality of the continuum). The power set of a set S, together with the operations of union, intersection and complement, is a Σ-algebra over S and can be viewed as the prototypical example of a Boolean algebra.

  3. Cantor's theorem - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Cantor's_theorem

    Much more significant is Cantor's discovery of an argument that is applicable to any set, and shows that the theorem holds for infinite sets also. As a consequence, the cardinality of the real numbers, which is the same as that of the power set of the integers, is strictly larger than the cardinality of the integers; see Cardinality of the ...

  4. Equinumerosity - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Equinumerosity

    Assuming the existence of an infinite set N consisting of all natural numbers and assuming the existence of the power set of any given set allows the definition of a sequence N, P(N), P(P(N)), P(P(P(N))), … of infinite sets where each set is the power set of the set preceding it. By Cantor's theorem, the cardinality of each set in this ...

  5. Cardinal number - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Cardinal_number

    A bijective function, f: X → Y, from set X to set Y demonstrates that the sets have the same cardinality, in this case equal to the cardinal number 4. Aleph-null , the smallest infinite cardinal In mathematics , a cardinal number , or cardinal for short, is what is commonly called the number of elements of a set .

  6. Cantor's diagonal argument - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Cantor's_diagonal_argument

    A generalized form of the diagonal argument was used by Cantor to prove Cantor's theorem: for every set S, the power set of S—that is, the set of all subsets of S (here written as P(S))—cannot be in bijection with S itself. This proof proceeds as follows: Let f be any function from S to P(S). It suffices to prove f cannot be surjective.

  7. Cardinality - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Cardinality

    Although E is a proper subset of N, both sets have the same cardinality. N does not have the same cardinality as its power set P(N): For every function f from N to P(N), the set T = {n∈N: n∉f(n)} disagrees with every set in the range of f, hence f cannot be surjective.

  8. Controversy over Cantor's theory - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Controversy_over_Cantor's...

    The set of all subsets of N is denoted by P(N), the power set of N. Cantor generalized his argument to an arbitrary set A and the set consisting of all functions from A to {0, 1}. [4] Each of these functions corresponds to a subset of A, so his generalized argument implies the theorem: The power set P(A) has greater cardinality than A.

  9. Cantor's paradox - Wikipedia

    en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Cantor's_paradox

    Then (in the von Neumann formulation of cardinality) C is a set and therefore has a power set 2 C which, by Cantor's theorem, has cardinality strictly larger than C. Demonstrating a cardinality (namely that of 2 C) larger than C, which was assumed to be the greatest cardinal number, falsifies the definition of C. This contradiction establishes ...